italian version

 

Social Contract

 
 

Giovanni De Sio Cesari

www.giovannidesio.it

 

 

 

Historical Aspects
The idea that society originates from an agreement among individuals (commonly referred to as the social contract) emerged in the 18th century. According to this notion, the State was established through a pact at a particular point in historical evolution, whereby individuals relinquished a limited portion of their absolute freedom, which they had enjoyed in nature, in exchange for significant advantages offered by a structured state order. This idea gained considerable popularity as it effectively constrained the power of the State (specifically the monarchical absolutism of that era). Thus, the State became a contract that everyone was bound to respect; if the sovereign failed to do so, the subjects, now identified as citizens, had the right to depose the non-compliant monarch. Above all, the powers of the State were constrained by the contract, with the inalienable rights of citizens—such as life and property—taking precedence, and later on, many additional rights being included. This concept was highly influential in the battle against the prevailing notion of a sovereign ruling by divine right, wherein the monarch was viewed as a representative of God, to whom obedience was due, even for religious reasons; the monarch would be accountable to God for their actions.

However, the idea of the social contract was gradually surpassed during the 19th century because it did not align with reality. Human beings have always existed within a societal framework; outside of society is an abstraction. In fact, primitive and ancient societies were much more cohesive and intrusive. Historians of the 19th century, such as Burckhardt, believed that only with the Renaissance did individualism begin to emerge. the

Individuality, and from this arose European primacy.
The premise of the social contract is that the individual and the community are opposing and autonomous entities, almost like two separate states, as was sometimes said, but in reality, one exists because the other exists: that is, there is no individual outside of society (of which the State is an organ) and there is no community without the individual. Therefore, we cannot consider the individual and the State (community) as separate entities: they are all closely interconnected. The individual impacts the community and vice versa; the challenge is to find a balance point that will always be variable.
The concept of the social contract has been recently revisited by some schools of thought that self-identify as liberal and view the democratic concept as distinct from liberal, meaning that there are liberal and non-liberal democracies, depending on whether the power of the State stops at the person and also at the citizen’s property.
At this point, it is necessary to clarify the meaning of certain terms that are used in a very varied and sometimes confusing way.
In the 1800s, the terms liberal and democratic indicated a lesser or greater radicalism in the fight against absolutism, while today "liberal" seems almost vanished from political language: I see no major party bearing this title, neither in Italy nor in the West. In my opinion, the concept is of a bygone era.
In America, we have "liberal" with a different meaning from our "liberal": we could translate it as "progressive."
It is important not to confuse "liberal" with "libertarian": liberal, in the sense of democratic, means that political power is chosen in pluralistic elections in an atmosphere of broad freedom and is opposed to the old absolutisms, communisms, fascisms, and other dictatorships.
Libertarian, on the other hand, supports free economic enterprise, as opposed to socialism, which advocates State intervention in the economy.
Thus, "liberal" in the democratic sense is distinct from "libertarian" in the sense of supporting free enterprise: in fact, all four combinations exist.
There are non-democratic and libertarian regimes (fascisms), non-democratic and non-libertarian regimes (communisms), libertarian and democratic regimes (USA), democratic and socialist systems (Scandinavians).
Libertarians and socialists are general trends: for instance, the first welfare state was promoted by Bismarck, who certainly was not a socialist. The Meloni government has not eliminated all State intervention but aims to reduce it.
Currently, what predominates in economics is the welfare state, which seeks to balance State action and free enterprise.
On the other hand, 19th-century liberals spoke of freedom but always within the framework of morality (i.e., social rules); indeed, they generally positioned themselves as champions of ethics in opposition to the aristocracy, which often ignored it (e.g., The Day by Parini, The Duties of Man by Mazzini and Pellico).
The very few who argued that everyone could do whatever they wanted were extreme supporters of absolute power (beyond good and evil, like Nietzsche, who certainly was not a liberal).

Individual and Collective
The theory of the natural and original absolute freedom of the individual, from which the social contract would arise, is an abstraction contrary to human nature, which is essentially social.
In fact, if it is not accepted in any society, from primitive to postmodern, it means that it is impossible to apply and contrary to nature. It is like saying that judges and punishments are unnecessary in society: the fact that they exist everywhere, albeit in very different forms, means that they are necessary and consistent with human nature.
First, we note that since everyone has their own opinion, common decisions require an authority according to mechanisms that vary by group. For example, in the family, parents ultimately decide for minor children. Obviously, the decision can be considered appropriate or not, depending on the perspectives of the children and observers.
It can also happen that decisions are made out of parental selfishness (which rarely happens in families).
Similarly, the State, which impacts the individual’s life far less than the family, functions this way. Decisions by a right-wing government are not shared by those on the left, and vice versa; a measure will always seem good to some and bad to others: a matter of opinion. Then the majority decides through voting.
Unlike the family, politicians often make decisions with more attention to their interests than general ones: certainly, the government is not comparable to the natural love of parents.
There are mechanisms in place to limit these realities: we are in a democracy, meaning the government is judged by the public through voting and thus has every interest in satisfying it.
Our Constitution (and democratic ones in general) is defined as "personalistic," meaning society-oriented: the rights it enunciates are about participating in national life, not doing whatever one pleases.
The perspective is that the Republic must remove all obstacles preventing true and full participation in national life (for example, mandatory schooling). Also, every individual right presupposes a collective duty, that is, all of us: the right to health implies that we all pay for the medical expenses of those who fall ill.

Public and Private
All democrats believe in freedom of thought, free elections, and rights that allow actions, even if these sometimes negatively impact society within certain limits. However, no party supports the idea that one's body or home is outside State jurisdiction. It would make no sense: it would be impossible, for example, to punish criminals, enforce compulsory military service, or understand why healthcare should be guaranteed.
Concerning property, public works could not be carried out if a single owner refused to cede their property, making execution impossible.
Freedom of action can be broader in prosperous situations, and for this reason, rights are compressed in times of difficulty (widespread poverty, war, emergencies).
Consider a law that bans something (e.g., drugs): the rationale is that it harms others. This rationale will be accepted by some and rejected by others; there may even be some government interest, but that is the justification.
The idea that property was a natural right (and what would that mean?) dates back to the 1700s and has since been surpassed. By "natural," we mean what comes from nature, such as attraction to the opposite sex, love for children, the desire for well-being, and, above all, sociality.
Property depends on societal rules: in the Inca Empire, our feudal Middle Ages, and shogunate Japan, land, a fundamental property, belonged to the State (the emperor), which granted it for use.
In primitive societies, one might assume prey belonged to the hunter, but it belonged to the whole group. Even today, what I earn does not belong solely to me but also to my family, and furthermore, the State takes an average of 40%.
Modernly, I own the house inherited from my parents according to our society's rules (in the past, there was primogeniture, men inherited more than women; today, there are various inheritance tax measures). My money is just paper (now primarily numbers on a computer), but it holds value according to society's rules, earned and guaranteed according to these rules, and a significant portion (40% on average) is taken by the State.
Property is still guaranteed by the State; otherwise, anyone could evict me from my home, and it can be confiscated in cases of public necessity.
The real issue of property is that it involves not only the fruit of one’s labor but also rent, formerly land-based, now enterprise-based, a problem that was the foundation of major socialist movements (property as theft, surplus value theory).
Sometimes it is said that the State's authority should stop at the boundaries of private property (symbolically: the home). But laws are valid inside and outside the home: assaulting a woman is no less a crime at home than on the street, and if drug use were a crime, it would be inside or outside the home, as is drug dealing.
Different is being naked: outside the home is not allowed, but at home, it is. However, in this case, what is forbidden is being seen naked, so if I am at home but in a garden or terrace visible to others, it would be a crime.

Conclusion
The central point of all this is that one’s freedom ends where others’ begins. This statement is attributed (apparently erroneously) to 18th-century thinkers. But what does it mean? Almost every action we take (except for a few trivial exceptions) always impacts others (and vice versa), so we would essentially have no choices to make. In reality, this is not true, because only a small portion of our actions are regulated by society, and only a small portion of those regulations are enshrined in State laws. And this occurs in every society.
What truly distinguishes modern democracy from the absolutist regimes of the present and past is that every citizen can freely express their ideas and, through elections, choose governments. These actions are free not because they do not impact others for better or worse; indeed, it is precisely this way that the individual can clearly and incisively influence the community. Democracy does not allow unjust and/or illegal acts, but it is the citizens (in the majority) who determine what is just and legal.
The political debate is about what rules are the best, the fairest, and the most advantageous for the community, not about a supposed untouchable autonomy of the individual and their assets, which no society recognizes.